Disability in Augustine's De Civitate Dei
In
the course of pressing toward the best interpretation of the
inscription at Delphi, Plutarch’s character Ammonius
characterizes those who are not spiritually alert as being in a state
of sleep.
Philo writes of Abraham’s turning from astrology to Yahweh as
opening the eye and awakening from sleep.
The figures of speech denoting a state of lack of spiritual awareness
which are used by both of these writers are those conditions which
are common to all of humanity. They thereby imply that spiritual
unawareness is a potentially universal condition, a part of human
nature. Such figures of speech do not imply that spiritual
unawareness is linked to physically disabling conditions, or that
such disabilities are a recompense for any particular transgressions.
A
complaint of many disability advocates today, though, is that
Christian utterance often symbolizes the state of not being
spiritually aware with figures of physical disability: for example,
being blind, lame, dumb, or deaf. This creates an implication that to
have a disability is to be in a sinful state. A particularly glaring
(and popular) example comes from John Newton:
I
once was lost, but now am found;
was
blind, but now I see.
The
judgmental attitude of disability images is problematic, and so is
their particularity. The universality of sleep makes it more
difficult for any given person to disassociate themselves from the
lack of spiritual awareness expressed by Plutarch and Philo. It is
clear from these examples that not being spiritually alert does not
need to be symbolized in terms of physical disability, nor need one
correlate physical disability with a state of sinfulness. The use of
such more universal and less judgmental images by non-Christian
writers aroused my interest in the use of disability images and the
attitudes toward disability in early Christian writers. This paper is
the result of that interest.
Augustine’s
City
of God
is the focal point of this study. As a response to the sack of Rome,
and the suffering which resulted from it, the book deals with
concrete issues. Augustine’s concern for suffering is real, but
it is also the springboard for a wider and deeper inquiry: “this
question has a wide extension, for many people are continually
troubled by the fact that the everyday gifts of God, as also the
disasters of humanity, happen to those of good and those of evil life
without distinction.”
The book is a massive exposition of Christian faith, and covers a
wide range of material. As a mature work, it is a vehicle for a
summary of Augustine’s thought. The Enchiridion
provides a complement, giving practical, straightforward advice.
There are also scattered references to Augustine’s other works
to fill in details, and the use of secondary sources for interpretive
guidance and background.
In
this paper, I first examine Augustine’s theory of humanity (I),
and then some practical examples he deals with that relate to
disability issues (II). Then I look at his exposition of the
resurrection body (III), and finally, I consider the human
obligations and responses that Augustine sees as appropriate (IV).
The issues considered here are views of the body, images of not being
spiritually alert, and considerations of how these are correlated and
how they are used in practical settings. Through this lens, we are
able to come to some conclusions about Augustine’s view on the
role of God in disabilities, and the human reaction.
City
of God
and the other works contain few direct references to disabilities.
Augustine does make use of the state of blindness to refer to
spiritual unawareness, and also discusses the condition of persons
with disabling conditions after the resurrection. These will be
examined in detail further on, but, through much of this survey, we
gain far more information from related discussions, such as the
causes that underlie any untoward event. How ought these to be
viewed, and the person treated? Does any physical ailment or injury
create a permanent stain on the soul, or is it an affliction of the
body which can be treated—either now by humans or later in a
restoration (or fulfillment) of perfection at the resurrection? The
first area of concern, though, is the structure of the world in which
all of this occurs, which provides a foundation for understanding why
things are the way they are.
I
In
Augustine’s thought, God holds an overwhelming position.
Augustine notes that the first article of the creed expresses belief
in God Almighty, and that such belief requires human acknowledgment
that God may do whatever God pleases.
God is omnipotent and omniscient; although God knows “all
things before they happen,” humans still act in free will, for
events would not occur “without our volition.”
God does not act at random—there is an order to the universe.
Humans cannot understand this order, but God knows it perfectly.
Although God acts in accordance with this order, God is its master,
and is in control of it, not subject to it.
Augustine thus removes life from the deterministic ravages of an
impersonal, uncaring fate or destiny, and maintains God’s
supreme and complete power, while building a foundation for humans to
freely and inevitably choose to err.
God’s
omniscience means that God foreknew Adam’s sin, but it is a
sign of God’s justice that God brought good out of that
situation.
God does not seek evil in any circumstance. God’s justice is
thus made an absolute. As we will see, humans suffer punishment, but
this punishment is for our own good, and not administered for
retribution. Thus we can trust that whatever God does is intended to
bring the best results out of human errors. This weakens any
arguments that a disability may have been sent to a specific person
as punishment. Someone might have a disability as the best way to
deal with some other situation, but it would seem (here, at least)
that God would not decree a disability simply as retribution.
The
intent behind this argument is a demonstration of God’s power,
but it also shows how Augustine shares with the non-Christian writers
cited earlier a foundational belief that any explanations offered
about the cosmos must attribute proper worthiness to the divine. In
particular, a good God cannot be the cause of evil.
The concept of divine worthiness gives Augustine a foundation to
understand the world. The pattern which he outlines in the
Enchiridion
is: God is good; the world is created by God; so the world must be
good.
And if creation is good, then one’s attitude to the body, as an
aspect of creation, is radically re-oriented. In City
of God,
Augustine says that the body is created by God and is good.
This pattern, of course, differs greatly from the prevalent Platonic
view of the Roman world in Augustine’s day. This view, which
many in the early church accepted, held that the physical world is
inherently flawed and the body is a burden to the soul. Augustine
overturned this view, as well as that of the dichotomy of body and
soul, which went with it.
Although
he affirms the goodness of creation, Augustine is acutely aware that
“the whole of man’s life is pain.”
Since God cannot bring about evil, the obvious question is then,
whence evil? The answer, which seems like a theological tight-rope
walker’s act, is worked out through Platonic images and
presumptions, leading to a very un-Platonic conclusion. Evil is
defined as a change wherein good is diminished; its origin is the
absence of God’s goodness. The creation is from God, who is
unchanging, but it is not exactly like God: it shows the order and
beauty of the divine, but it is not unchangeable.
From earlier writings of Augustine, we learn that variety is required
by this changeable order, so differences within the world are to be
expected. These differences include the relative lack of good in some
things. The creation can yet be called good, because evil does not
attack the divinely good order of the cosmos. Thus something may
occur which to one person is evil without reflecting on the order of
the whole.
In City
of God,
Augustine emphasizes that good is diminished by acts of human will,
not by acts of God.
Following this, one could consider an individual’s disability
to be evil, without charging God with inflicting the evil, for it is
a variation in the mutable created world. This would not upset the
order of the world as a whole. So then, if evil in any form is not
from God, disabilities are not divine punishment (this is, of course,
to the extent that disabilities are considered an evil, which I take
for granted—I have yet to find any instance in personal
acquaintance or in literature where a disabled person seriously
considers their disability to be good of itself. This is not to deny
that good may come out of a disability or that some writers who do
not experience disabilities have some notion of their hidden
benefits). Nor do disabilities give cause for affront to anyone: they
are anomalies of the physical world, something that has changed
within the physical realm— they are not cosmic errors or
disruptions in some sort of dangerous person from which “normal”
humans must be shielded.
We
have also noted that Augustine attributes evil to acts of human will.
According to Augustine’s reading of Genesis, humans were
created with all parts of the body under control of the will. This
control was disrupted by desire, and this disruption led to the
Fall.
As a result of the Fall, humans suffer a schism between intelligence
(knowledge, mind) and will (love); thus their sense of the order of
creation has been lost. This disorder is the mark of sin, and is
displayed as humans turn from the Creator to created things—in
short, the search for happiness is directed to the self rather than
God, which is an act of pride. The soul’s presumptuous
self-absorption and mis-directed love, concupiscence, leads humans to
cosmic disorientation.
We
may also note that it is the body’s corruptibility, not its
presence, which is a burden to the soul. Sin originated in the soul’s
insubordination, which resulted in the corruption of the flesh. Not
only were bodies not the source of sin, they were not created as
punishment in the fall; their corruption is the punishment, not the
cause, of sin.
The necessary cure for the disordered human person is not to shun the
body, but to bring it under proper control.
This
disorder is a condition that is common to all, and the pervasiveness
of pain is evidence of the Fall and the resulting punishment. As
Miles notes, the idea of original sin is not popular these days, but
it does allow for a “gentler interpretation” of the human
situation than theories which place all of the blame on personal
responsibility.
This would be particularly true of disabilities. They are the result
of sin, but that sin is endemic. Therefore, Augustine would, I think,
strongly caution us against linking a disability with some
transgression. As we will soon see, Augustine does not deny that a
disability or injury may come to a person as punishment, but he also
notes that there are many other causes, and that humans are not in a
position to judge why any particular event occurs. The question is
less why some untoward event befalls some people than why such events
do not happen to all people.
As
Augustine surveys the wide range of disaster which befalls humans, we
can discern three areas of inquiry: what the specific cause of a
particular affliction might be (and, consequently, how we should view
such a person), how a person who is afflicted should respond to God
as the omnipotent Creator, and how others should react to an
afflicted person. The opening pages of City
of God
give us a broad outline for these categories. After charging us not
to blame God for disasters and then claim human credit for good,
Augustine tells us that afflictions are God’s method of
correction and teaching,
and perhaps, as with Job, a test to learn the degree of
“disinterested devotion” to the Creator.
He also tells us that both good and evil events befall the righteous
as well as the wicked, indiscriminately.
Bad events are not spoken of as punishment for a particular moral
evil. That some are corrective would indicate that there is a degree
of divine response to evil acts, but some are examinations of the
righteous. So it is a dangerous thing for humans to attribute any
cause, for, to Augustine, only God knows the complete story. Thus,
there can be no direct correlation between bad things happening and
sinfulness. It is also a dangerous thing for humans to blame God for
an ill and then credit themselves for good—the person with a
disability who in some way overcomes their handicap does so by God’s
grace, not their own effort.
One
thing Augustine is sure of, throughout City
of God,
is that the grace of Christ is what humans, as suffering sinners,
should seek.
We will return to the human response to divine grace after surveying
how Augustine’s foundations work out in practical examples.
II
The
claim that the soul’s control of the body is the origin of sin,
and thereby determinative of the person’s condition, is
strengthened as Augustine deals with the case of women raped in the
Roman disaster. Flowing from the idea that sin resulted from a
decision of the will, Augustine says that one’s purity is
determined in his or her mind. He tells us that if the mind is
controlled by virtue, this control consecrates the body, and what
another does to the body cannot bring blame to the sufferer. If
purity could be lost on the basis of a physical action alone, it
would not be a matter of virtue, but a simple physical quality,
subject to the transitoriness of all physical attributes. The person
who has virtue may endure evil without consenting to it, even when it
involves their body. One cannot decide what will happen to the body,
but can decide what the mind will accept.
The sufferings of the women are not to be equated with a loss of
virtue, which would also say that they are not to undergo the further
sufferings of social stigma. There are at least two lessons
applicable to our interest here. First: since the mind controls the
body, this aspect is determinative of one’s virtue, not the
status of the body. A person who lives with a disabled body is not
per
se
outside of divine grace or favor, nor is such a body a sign of wrath
sent from God. If the mind is attuned to God, the condition of the
body is secondary.
Second, Augustine is extremely compassionate toward those who suffer
physical ills. In either case, their physical condition is not to be
used to exclude them from being considered whole people.
The
idea of control is also important because it lies behind Augustine’s
use of the term “blind” to refer to spiritual unawareness
(which we should note is infrequent). John Newton certainly seems to
link blindness to sinfulness—and vision is a frequent metaphor
for spiritual and mental understanding elsewhere. Does Augustine have
in mind a similar equation of an involuntary defect in vision with
sin? As the basis for an answer, we may note how Miles explains the
theory of vision used by Plato, which persisted through Augustine’s
day. As she does so, she demonstrates that the careless use of this
figure, if drawn from the literature of antiquity, is a mis-reading
of the process which was thought to be behind it. The first clue here
is in Plato’s use of the sense of sight. Vision is the sharpest
(o)cuta/th)
of the sensations. Beauty flows naturally, like a current (r(eu~ma),
into the soul through the eyes. The vision of earthly beauty causes
the soul to recall something of its once-heavenly placement and
hopefully leads it to seek true beauty (e.g., the divine realm).
We see that vision is certainly a spiritual matter, but the theory of
its operation stands apart from typical sense perceptions. One’s
basic knowledge comes from sensation. But this knowledge is not true
knowledge, for it deals with the mutable objects of the physical
world. The true sensation, and what can be really known, is the
result of the soul’s use of the body to bond to these sensed
objects.
As the viewer concentrates on an object, the projections of the
object are transmitted to the viewer, creating a momentary unity. The
soul has a store of images of external objects, so it chooses what to
concentrate on, based on its memory. Thus the soul is an active agent
in vision; unlike the ear, it does not simply respond
indiscriminately to stimuli as they come. The eye, as an active part
of the soul, must be trained, exercised, and cleansed of its wrong
affections.
This model of vision emphasizes the importance of the viewer’s
initiative and direction, which is a reminder of the soul’s
control of the body. So when Augustine uses the term “blind”
to refer to someone who refuses to “see” the truth,
it would seem that he is using a metaphor that does not refer to an
involuntary disability, but to those who refuse, through their
misguided will, to exert a positive influence over their body. This
refusal is an example of the continuing effort of disordered human
souls to direct their own course.
Miracles
are always a subject of interest when disability is discussed. To
some observers, that some disabled person does not receive a
miraculous healing is a sign that the person lacks religious faith.
Some see a healing miracle as a sign that some dark, deep sin has
been forgiven. To the disabled person, there is often a perception in
miracle stories that the person involved stands in need of a cure,
and is not whole unless they are restored, thereby creating classes
of able or whole versus
disabled or lacking, which widen the supposed lack of faith or
forgiveness.
Augustine
tells us here, as he does in other areas, that a complete explanation
is beyond human understanding. For one thing, miracles of healing
may not be granted because the wrong motive stands behind a request.
Religion is not about the benefits of this life, but the next, and
miracles can bring a wrong emphasis, resulting in confusion on this
point. But they may also not be granted because a suffering person
should display the courage of faith.
This is generally a positive approach for a person with a
disability, since there is no expectation that a person with a
disability will receive healing as proof of faith. But Augustine’s
insistence on repeating miracle stories (as in Book 22 of City
of God)
leads to an area of discomfort for many disabled persons today. The
person who has received such a miraculous healing (which may be taken
broadly, to include “supernatural” efforts to live with
their body and overcome the condition in which they live) might be
singled out as blessed in everyday practice. This leads, albeit
unintentionally, back to the expectation that a faithful person will
be healed.
Augustine
further questions whether miracles were even needed in his day, for
they were signs meant to bring belief in Christ in a world where he
was not known. This further removes their occurrence from anything
related to personal sins, or the “need” for physical
healing to become whole. Then he notes that there are miracles in his
day, and reports on several. He reports a cure of blindness without
any comment on or reference to the symbolism of blindness as a
spiritual state. The same occurs when he reports the cure of a
paralytic: there is no reference to a spiritual renewal, only the
setting right of a bodily function. Also instructive is the story of
seven brothers and three sisters, residents of Caesarea, who were
cursed by their mother because she felt ignored by them. They were
“afflicted with a frightful trembling of the limbs.”
Wherever they went, they were stared at, and they took to wandering.
Two were healed (at different times) at the shrine of St. Stephen in
Hippo after “praying that God would now be appeased and restore
them to their former health.” In all of these, Augustine’s
interest is not the healing itself, but making God’s power
known.
The miracles are done by God, to show that the Christian faith, and
specifically the resurrection of Christ, is true, and to proclaim the
martyred saints to be valid intercessors.
They are not done for the sake of the person healed. This might be
taken as a slight, for the person’s sufferings do not seem to
be of great interest. By way of reply, we might propose that
Augustine takes the existence of human suffering as a given, for, as
we have noted before, suffering is universal. He is simply not
interested in dwelling on the details, because there is nothing
unusual about them—and that is significant of itself, for it
says that he finds nothing to take great notice of in the existence
of disabilities. They simply happen in the course of human life. We
may also note that there is also no link of healing a physical
ailment with forgiveness of sin in the first two incidents recounted.
The latter story is more problematic in this regard. We may note,
however, that this was a healing of an acquired condition, not a
birth disability. We recall that Augustine allows that physical ills
may be a punishment for transgression, but that we cannot always
reach such a conclusion. To the one recounting the story, the cause
is very clear here, and we cannot deny that some people suffer
because they have made bad choices. But not everyone suffers because
of sin, and thus, overall, disability remains an enigma.
It is
also significant that miracles and the validation of the Christian
faith are tied specifically to the resurrection. Not only are
miracles possible because of the resurrection, they are a sign of its
truth to Augustine, as well as a statement on the value of the body.
We now turn to that direction.
III
The
claim that sin originates in the soul, and that the body is good, is
a reversal of the ideas that had permeated Christendom. Now we meet
another reversal of commonly held ideas, one that follows from those
already presented: his claim about the importance of bodies. We may
find this claim revealed in the stories of miracles, the resurrection
of Christ, and the expectation of a bodily resurrection to judgment.
These themes may be seen most strikingly in Augustine’s
expositions on the nature of the resurrection body. In Book 22 of
City
of God
and in portions of the Enchiridion,
Augustine defends the doctrine of a general bodily resurrection. His
interest in this doctrine arises from 1 Corinthians 15: the
resurrection of the body is a cornerstone of the Christian faith, and
the resurrection of Christ is the paradigm and guarantee of the
resurrection of each person. For Paul and Augustine, this central
idea stood in opposition to Platonic sensibility: why would one want
to be reunited to the body from which they had so long sought
liberation?
In
this light, it is natural that Augustine would take up a defense of
the doctrine of resurrection as a central feature of the conclusion
of City
of God.
In the course of this defense, he deals with what seem to be
objections to the doctrine, especially its presumed logical
contradictions, which had been raised by opponents. A great part of
this defense is the question of how differences among human bodies,
especially “deformities and defects,” will be handled in
the resurrection.
One of the questions dealt with at length comes from the statement of
Luke 21.18 that “not a hair of your head will perish”
(NRSV).
To
understand how Augustine approaches this issue, we must return to the
earlier discussion of the fundamental necessity that one’s
conceptions must be worthy of the divine. Another issue of worthiness
is how to interpret scriptures and other religious sources, such as
myths. Plutarch argued that the Greek myths cannot be read literally:
this would irreverently demean the divine.
Allegorical reading as a means of understanding was also one method
used by Augustine. To read all of the Christian scriptures literally
would result in blasphemy and impiety.
The promise in Luke is a place where a literal reading would be
absurd (and thereby, impious); the issue is the perfection of the
resurrection body, and the promise is about “number of hairs,
not length.”
The promise that not a hair will perish is taken to mean that one’s
natural physical potential will be fulfilled at the resurrection.
Nothing that is essential to the person will be lost. For example,
those who died as infants will be resurrected according to the
potential they held for growth into adults. Here, Augustine likens
the potential with which humans are conceived and born to a “pattern
on a loom.”
Although humans will be resurrected with the body that their
potential would have allowed them to have in their prime, he sees age
differences as insignificant, for there will be no weakness of mind
or body at the resurrection.
Augustine
is quite certain that the resurrection will be of a physical body,
but one very different from the present one. The absence of defects
in the resurrection body extends to incorruptibility, lack of
subjection to the misleading of concupiscence, and the impossibility
of its becoming endangered or diseased.
Although Augustine says that the resurrected body will have no
defects, he cannot say how that will work out, or what will happen,
in every imaginable case. For example, he does not know what will
happen with stillbirths, but if they are resurrected, it will be to
their potential had they lived.
Looking at the case of Siamese twins, he says that birth defects and
deformations “shall at the resurrection be restored to the
normal shape of man.” The principle of restoration is not that
of restoring all the hair or nails ever cut off, for restoration need
not be replacement to be complete. It is rather a reshaping, as if
the metal of a deformed statue were melted and re-shaped into the
figure which the sculptor had intended. Therefore, certain physical
features, such as stature, build, and features, will be retained, so
that a person is recognizable. However, nothing that would “jar
upon their sensibilities,” a category in which he includes many
physical anomalies, will remain, and everything will be “graceful
and becoming.” Inequalities that remain will not be
problematic—they will be variations that work together, as the
difference in voices contributes to musical harmony.
Augustine allows one exception to the general physical restoration
and renewal: the wounds of the martyrs, which will not be a
deformity, but “glorious,” will remain.
This attention to the details of how the body will be raised is one
indication of its importance.
But
why is the body so important? Augustine gives the answer to this,
beginning with a discussion of burial in an earlier book of City
of God:
“actual bodies are certainly not to be treated with contempt,
since we wear them in a much closer and more intimate way than any
clothing.”
At another point, he says that “a man’s body is not mere
adornment, or external convenience; it belongs to his very nature as
a man.”
The resurrected body, however, will not be corruptible, so it will
not be at odds with the soul—and Augustine is careful to say
that it will be a body of flesh, not a spirit.
The body must be resurrected because the soul needs one to function.
In
the course of dealing with the importance of the body, Augustine
overturns another presumption, giving us an insight on what was
probably the most significant disability of the ancient world—being
female. Augustine had previously undermined the basis for
perceptions of femaleness as inferior: not only were bodies not the
result of the Fall, as we have seen, but humans had been created as
male and female, and (albeit under vastly different circumstances)
would have had children if they had remained in paradise.
Now he says that not only will the resurrection body will be one of
flesh, but sexual identity will be preserved, because “a
woman’s sex is not a defect, it is natural.”
Women are not, just because of their bodies, to be considered
inferior to men. Not only are bodies themselves necessary, their
sexual distinctions are perfectly normal. In one stroke, Augustine
has overturned many of the presumptions of his day.
We
have seen that Augustine’s portrayal of human suffering, in all
of its dimensions, is ruthlessly and consistently realistic. This is
welcome, but also creates some problems. Although some would like to,
we cannot deny the physical reality of disability and its effects on
bodies just because some other effects (e.g., social stigma) are
undesirable. It is to his credit that Augustine does not single out
anyone here. Everyone suffers. Some suffer more than others, and
humans are in no position to try to understand why this is, but
neither are they to single any person out as either righteous or a
sinner based on physical disability or any other suffering.
The
first problem arises is that this is an ideal, of course. For those
who are oppressed, Augustine offers no recourse other than to trust
God for their happiness to come in the future life (which is not, for
him, a “weak” option, as we shall see). Nor is this a
justification of oppression. Miles notes that Augustine’s
concept of social order is parallel to the workings of a human being:
it is complex and this necessitates an order. In this order,
inequality is necessary, but it is not something to be glorified or
justified. Those with greater positions are placed there to be
servants.
But to one who lives under such conditions, it seems sometimes that a
future reward is the self-seeking justification of a system that
promotes inequity for someone’s gain.
The
second problem arises from Augustine’s statements about the
body being the nature of the person. Augustine took a bold step with
his assertion that femaleness is part of nature, and that women will
be resurrected as women. For all this, as he discusses the
restoration of defects in the body, he seems to overlook the fact
that one’s body as a whole is part of their nature. If the
person has lived with a disabled body, the characteristics of that
body frame a life, and so become part of the person’s nature.
What becomes of that nature at the resurrection, if one very
important part is changed? If a person who walks with difficulty is
suddenly able to run, there will be more changes than just an
increase of mobility and transformation of an eyesore. His interests,
defined by a previously forced degree of sedentary life, could
change. He could take up an interest in sports, and leave behind a
scholarly life. The body is indeed part of the person’s
nature—and the nature is also part of the body. If one changes,
so does the other, and the changes reach far beyond bodily repair.
While it is doubtful that one who lives with a disabled body and
expects an Augustinian resurrection would not want that physical
restoration which Augustine speaks of, it would seem that Augustine
has not considered the effect of these changes to that disabled
person.
One
also wonders, if the wounds of martyrs are glorious, and being female
is a matter of nature (and both are conditions which will remain in
the resurrection), why a disability cannot remain as a glorious sign
of perseverance, or a natural matter that contributes harmoniously to
variety. If disabilities are viewed as something to be cured, it does
not especially matter if they will be cured now or later: they are
problems,
and not a contribution to variety. Therefore, they are deviations,
and given the human tendencies which Augustine so well describes, can
easily become a source of the unjust treatment which he cautions
against. Again, it is not that the disabled person might not desire
the changes described by Augustine, but the foundational attitude
that says such changes are necessary (for whatever reason) reveals an
approach that can undermine everything else the author has to say
about equal treatment.
This
caution is important because Augustine says that those who do not
suffer should be wary of thinking themselves better off for that, a
warning that should not be lost.
Further advancing this warning is a discussion on how one should
treat those injured in war, stating that neither holiness nor being a
person is a matter of a correctly functioning, complete body:
the
body is not holy just because its parts are intact, or because they
have not undergone any handling. Those parts may suffer violent
injury by accidents of various kinds, and sometimes doctors seeking
to effect a cure may employ treatment with distressing visible
effects.
This
also tells that in Augustine’s view, neither accidents nor
medical manipulations change the essential goodness of the body. Nor
would it seem that Augustine would criticize those who seek medical
relief for a condition. Although, given the state of medicine in his
day, the cure might be as bad as the disease, one need not endure a
condition that can be treated.
Augustine also tells us that physical beauty, while good and from
God, is not the most important characteristic a person can have, for
it is temporal. Those who place it above their love of God commit a
sin. True happiness is not found in the physical, but in an upright
life that attends to God.
As
Augustine tells about the resurrection body, he deals with the
troubles of the present body, and here we learn something of his view
on how disabilities occur: they are proof of the mortal life being
lived in a state of punishment. As such, they are part of the
universal experience of misery resulting from human disobedience. The
more obvious conditions serve to make this message clear and increase
our longing for the happiness that is to be found only with God.
This is a subject Augustine has brought up before, as when he asserts
that the cause of human misery is “nothing but his [humanity’s]
own disobedience to himself.”
Now he reaffirms that this suffering is universal, and comes to both
righteous and wicked persons. All persons suffer their deserved
punishment, and any one who thinks he does not suffer is probably not
heeding the call of God in his life. In Augustine’s
anthropology, humans are not divine; they are creatures of a God who
is both all-powerful and all-good.
As creatures, they have a place in the creation, and Augustine says
that they should stay within the boundaries defined by God. Pride of
any kind is totally out of place, given the human situation.
Furthermore, it is only divine mercy, and not any worthiness of one’s
own, that determines who will suffer.
Because
some degree of suffering, recognized or not, is common to all
humanity, one’s attitude is all-important. It is one’s
response to the events of life, especially the unpleasant ones, that
tells what one is really like, not physical beauty or some other
external perception. A good person will pray and praise through
suffering while a wicked one blasphemes, for suffering makes the good
to shine and the chaff to smoke.
IV
“What
matters is the nature of the sufferer, not the nature of the
sufferings.”
Augustine’s
discussion of suffering, miracles, the resurrection of the body, and
the place of humans in the cosmos tells us much about his reaction to
and view of disabilities, as well as suffering in general. He has
also told us something of how suffering comes to be. But when it is
all over, we must accept what happens in life, for understanding the
workings of the universe, knowing how a just God chooses one person
in mercy and rejects another, is ultimately an “insoluble
problem.”
This is not an obstacle to Augustine, for the person who entrusts his
life to God realizes that this world is not the realm of fulfillment.
Happiness comes only by living a life that gives due regard to God,
and even then one realizes that a true state of happiness will only
arrive after death.
True hope is that which is placed in God’s promise of the
future resurrection. The good person neither rejoices in good things
in this life, nor allows affliction to overwhelm him, for the wicked
are punished by misfortune as much as they are corrupted by good.
The universality of suffering is further extended as Augustine
reminds us that there is nothing “extraordinary” about
the sufferings of his age, for the same sorts of things have happened
throughout history.
I
have noted places where the effect of Augustine’s arguments
could lead to more suffering, and it seems that his response is to
live with it. This could be considered a matter of not resisting the
status
quo,
the easy way, reflected in the aphorism “don’t rock the
boat.” But Augustine does not think of enduring suffering as an
easy thing—it is difficult, and can only be done with God’s
grace. The sign of a person rightly attuned to God is his strength to
endure suffering. For this reason, Augustine specifically rejects
suicide under any circumstance.
It should be noted that while several recent cases of persons asking
for liberalization of present laws on assisted suicide have gained
media coverage, there is (in my observation) substantial opposition
among the disabled community, out of concern that it could lead to
forced euthanasia of those with costly medical conditions.
Augustine’s affirmation that life is always worth living (at
least with God’s grace) is also an affirmation of the value of
every person’s life. No one is less human than another—and
here one of the greatest positive statements anyone could make about
disabilities.
Augustine
also asks us to “observe whether any disaster has happened to
the faithful and religious which did not turn out for their good,”
for the greatest gift, that of faith, cannot be lost due to physical
disasters.
Happiness is with God, not with the state of one’s body,
whether that body functions well or not (and, in many ways, no body
functions well, for they are all corrupt).
Although
there are some problems with his system, Augustine’s realistic
treatment of disability as part of a problematic human condition is
encouraging. Especially in the light of common notions, he takes some
great steps. Disabilities are not to be singled out as particular
category that signifies anything unusual beyond their appearance.
They are not, to any more or less extent than any other suffering
(which is universal), divine punishment for specific sins. They are
neither signs of danger nor of blessing. Inequity in distribution,
and the larger question of how God could send but not be responsible
for evil, remains a problem—but at least Augustine is honest
about this, and here he has nothing more or less to offer than many
others.
Augustine
might also say that the question is less why any disabling condition
or suffering might come to one person, than why it would not come to
all. In the long term, his affirmation that we all live in corrupt
bodies is more like the image of being asleep than being blind. To
have a disability is to be in a sinful state, but this not a
condition peculiar to anyone, for we all share in suffering and long
for the life to come.
-
- - - - - - - - - - - - - -
De
Trinitate 8.9, discussing what justice is, “But what does he
know it from? Has he ever seen it with his eyes, or some just body
perhaps, like a white or a black or a square or a round one? Who
would ever say such a thing? All he has ever seen with his eyes is
bodies, and it is only the mind in man that is just, and when a man
is called just he is called it from his mind and not his body. For
justice is a sort of beauty of mind by which many men are beautiful
even though they have ugly misshapen bodies. (Hill, p. 249)
On
Rebuke and Grace, NPNF 1, vol 5, ; ch 43 (14), if he who is rebuked
belongs to the number of the predestinated, rebuke may be to him a
wholesome medicine; and if he does not belong to that number, rebuke
may be to him a penal affliction. Under that very uncertainty,
therefore, it must of love be applied....
Bibliography
Augustine
of Hippo. Concerning
the City of God against the Pagans.
Translated by Henry Bettenson. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1972.
Augustine
of Hippo. Confessions.
2 vols. With an English translation by William Watts. Loeb Classical
Library Nos. 26 and 27. Cambridge: Harvard University Press and
London: William Heinemann, 1912.
Augustine
of Hippo. Enchiridion
[to Laurentius] on Faith, Hope and Love.
Translated by J. B. Shaw. Washington: Gateway Editions, Regnery
Publishing.
Babcock,
William S., ed. The
Ethics of St. Augustine.
Atlanta: Scholars Press, 1991.
Bottomley,
Frank. Attitudes
to the Body in Western Christendom.
London: Lepus, 1979.
Brown,
Peter. Augustine
of Hippo: a Biography.
Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967.
Brown,
Peter. The
Body and Society: Men, Women and Sexual Renunciation in Early
Christianity.
New York: Columbia University Press, 1988.
Bruning,
B. , M. Lamberigts, J. Van Houten, editors. Collectanea
Augustiniana.
Vol. 1. Louvain: Leuven University Press, 1990.
Haj,
F. Disability
in Antiquity.
New York: Philosophical Library, 1970. (*)
Marrou,
Henri Irénée. The
Resurrection and Saint Augustine’s Theology of Human Values.
Translated by Maria Consolata. The Saint Augustine Lecture Series,
no. 7. [Villanova PA]: Villanova Press, 1966.
Meynell,
Hugo A., editor. Grace,
Politics, and Desire: Essays on Augustine.
Calgary: University of Calgary Press, 1990.
Miles,
Margaret R. Augustine
on the Body.
American Academy of Religion Dissertation Series, No. 31. Missoula:
Scholars Press, 1979.
Miles,
Margaret R. “Vision: The Eye of the Body and the Eye of the
Mind in Saint Augustine’s De
trinitate and
Confessions,”
Journal
of Religion
63 (1983): 125-142.
Philo.
De
Abrahamo, De Iosepho, De Vita Mosis. With
an English translation by F. H. Colson. Loeb Classical Library, No.
289. Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press, 1935.
Plato.
Euthyphro,
Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus.
With an English translation by Harold North Fowler. Loeb Classical
Library, No. 36. Cambridge: Harvard University Press and London:
William Heinemann, 1914.
Plutarch.
Moralia,
Volume V.
With an English translation by Frank Cole Babbit. Loeb Classical
Library, No. 306. Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press,
1936.
Teske,
Roland J., S.J. “St. Augustine’s View of the Original
Human Condition in De
Genesi contra Manichaeos,”
Augustinian
Studies
22 (1991): 141-155.
United
Methodist Hymnal: Book of United Methodist Worship, The.
Nashville: The United Methodist Publishing House, 1989.
(*)
background information for study, not cited in paper